Skip to main content

Critical Thinking, Logic, and Argument: Chapter 8. The Syllogism

Critical Thinking, Logic, and Argument
Chapter 8. The Syllogism
    • Notifications
    • Privacy

“Chapter 8. The Syllogism” in “Critical Thinking, Logic, and Argument”

Chapter8The Syllogism

A syllogism, as we are using it, is a general argument pattern that involves two premises, a conclusion, and three terms.

Syllogisms come in many patterns, based on the terms and relationships.

Syllogism example 1 (Older than)

  • Premise 1: Bill is older than Galla.
  • Premise 2: Galla is older than Neetu.
  • _______________
  • Conclusion: Therefore, Bill is older than Neetu.

If we analyze this argument, we see that each premise has two terms (Bill and Galla in premise 1 and Galla and Neetu in premise 2) connected by a relation. The relation in all three statements is “_____ is older than _____.”

A proper syllogism will have a “middle term,” which is in premises 1 and 2 but not in the conclusion. Premises 1 and 2 share a middle term, which in this case is “Galla.” Galla’s relation to both Bill and Neetu (within the two premises) allows us to conclude something about Bill’s relation to Neetu.

8.1 Transitivity in a Syllogism

Syllogism example 2 (Containment)

  • Premise 1: Regina is in Saskatchewan.
  • Premise 2: Saskatchewan is in Canada.
  • _______________
  • Conclusion: Therefore, Regina is in Canada.

Here our middle term is “Saskatchewan,” and the relationship is one of containment. Containment, like the relation in example 1 (“_____ is older than _____”) is a transitive relationship. Transitivity is a relationship of ordering. If we know how things are ordered, then we can draw conclusions about the sequence. The order of example 1 is the order it would take to move from one place (Saskatoon) through another (Saskatchewan) to another (Canada).

Transitivity means that there’s a transfer of relationship between two things.

The transitivity of containment is demonstrated in figure 8.1. For containment, if A is inside of B and B is inside of C, then it stands to reason that A is inside of C. Through the middle term B, A gets the transitive property of being inside of C.

This relation also works with relative height. If we use “_____ is taller than _____,” we can construct a conduit for deduction about those who are being measured for height. You might want to draw your own visual about “_____ is taller than _____” for three people you know using a vertical line. So we can formulate a more specific definition of a transitive relation.

A transitive relation, R, has the property that for every three things a, b, and c to which R applies, if a is R to b and b is R to c, then a is R to c.

Let’s consider another example using the “_____ is greater than _____” relation. Is it also transitive?

Syllogism example 3 (Greater Than)

  • Premise 1: Nine is greater than seven.
  • Premise 2: Seven is greater than four.
  • _______________
  • Conclusion: Therefore, nine is greater than four.

A statement in the bottom left corner of the diagram says, “If A is inside B and B is inside C then A is inside C.” The top left has a small blue box [A] inside a pale blue box [B]. The top left has a box the same size as the pale blue box [B] inside a larger pale orange box [C]. And in the bottom right, the larger pale orange box [C] contains both the pale blue box [B] and the small blue box [A].

Figure 8.1 The transitivity of containment. Artwork by Jessica Tang.

This pattern should again demonstrate that properly formulated syllogisms with three terms and a transitive relationship are valid. To revisit that definition, if the premises are true, then the conclusion must be true—or there’s no possibility for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. “Is greater than” is a transitive relation. Notice that the two premises have the form “a is R to b” and “b is R to c,” and the conclusion has the form “a is R to c” (notice that “b” is the middle term).

Other relations that are transitive:

  • _____ = _____ (is equal to).
  • _____ > _____ (is greater than).
  • _____ ≤ _____ (is smaller than or equal to).
  • _____ ≥ _____ (is greater than or equal to).
  • if _____, then _____.
  • _____ is a species of _____.
  • _____ is heavier than _____.
  • _____ is poorer than _____.

8.2 Intransitivity

Of course, not every relation is transitive, and not every syllogism using a transitive relation is valid because the terms may not be in the right position in the argument.

Example of intransitive relation (Parent of)

  • Premise 1: Mary is the mother of Sarah.
  • Premise 2: Sarah is the mother of Mina.
  • _______________
  • Conclusion: Mary is the mother of Mina.

When we look at this relation, we can think of the connection through the middle term. Here, the middle term is “Sarah.” In this example, the problem is that the relation “_____ is the mother of _____” is not transitive: the parent of your parent is not your parent (they are your grandparent). You could also say the friend of my friend is not necessarily my friend: recall the phrase “the enemy of my enemy is my friend!” So be on the lookout for relationships that are not transitive. Similarly, If A loves B and B loves C, does it follow that A loves C? No, because “love” is a relation between two terms, or a binary relationship. Intransitive relationships block the validity of three-term syllogisms.

In an intransitive relationship, R has the property that for every three things a, b and c to which R applies, if a is R to b and b is R to c, then a is not R to c.

Sometimes a relationship is transitive, but it fails to produce a valid argument because of the location of the terms in the argument. Above, we discussed that “is taller than” was transitive, but it is only when the terms are in the right place. Let’s look at an example:

Example of intransitive “taller than” syllogism

  • Premise 1: My house (A) is taller than my car (B).
  • Premise 2: Your house (C) is taller than my car (B).
  • _______________
  • Conclusion: My house (A) is taller than your house (C).

All we know here is that both houses are taller than my car. This doesn’t give us any information on the relative heights of each other’s houses. Given the position of the terms, B (my car) fails to be a proper middle term. Its location blocks transitivity. If you read over the syllogism, do the premises make the case that our houses have a height difference? Could the premises be true andour houses be the same exact height (counter-example)? Yes. So it is possible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false, making it invalid.

In Chapters 9–12, we will spend some time looking at the traditional logic of terms also known as categorical logic. The syllogism pattern figures prominently in that logic in the form of the categorical syllogism. Here are two examples that are easily seen to be valid.

8.3 Containment Revisited

Consider the following example:

Example of categorical syllogism

  • Premise 1: All ducks are birds.
  • Premise 2: All birds are living creatures.
  • _______________
  • Conclusion: All ducks are living creatures.

In the first case, we can imagine drawing a circle around all the ducks and a larger circle around all the birds (fig. 8.2). If all ducks are birds, then the duck circle will be inside the bird circle. Similarly for all living creatures, the bird circle will be inside the circle around all the living creatures, and the duck circle will be inside that. When we draw a circle that is “living creatures,” we think of it as “the set of all things that qualify as living creatures.” So the size of “birds” within that set is not proportionate! But what the circles demonstrate is that birds are wholly contained within “living creatures.”

A small dark yellow circle with the label “ducks” sits inside a larger pale yellow circle with the label “birds,” which sits inside a larger and paler yellow circle bearing the label “living creatures.”

Figure 8.2 Containment relationship. Artwork by Jessica Tang.

Another transitive relationship that was mentioned above is the “if _____, then _____” relationship. Thinking of this explicitly as a transitive relationship allows us to understand the syllogism better.

Example of hypothetical syllogism

  • Premise 1: If you are a duck, then you are a bird.
  • Premise 2: If you are a bird, then you are a living creature.
  • _______________
  • Conclusion: Therefore, if you are a duck, then you are a living creature.

Looking back at figure 8.2, if you are in the smallest circle we demonstrated (ducks), then you must be in the other two circles (birds and living creatures). But if you are in the biggest circle (living creatures), it doesn’t necessarily follow that you are a duck (you could be a gorilla!). And if you are a bird, it doesn’t necessarily follow that you are a duck (you could be a warbler!). So you can go from the inside out with “if _____, then _____” but not from the outside in.

Here is another way to think about why this argument is valid: First of all, to say that all ducks are birds is tantamount to saying that if something is a duck, then it is a bird. And to say that all birds are living creatures is tantamount to saying that if something is a bird, then it is a living creature. In the case of the ducks argument, unless something changes and ducks are no longer birds and living creatures, the argument isn’t just valid, it is sound.

Key Takeaways

  • • Syllogisms consist of two premises, three terms, and a conclusion.
  • • For a syllogism to be valid, the relation must be transitive, and the terms must be in the proper location.
  • • Transitivity is an ordering relationship that helps us draw conclusions about terms in a sequence.
  • • Certain relationships are transitive (“taller than,” “older than,” “if _____, then _____,” etc.) and others are intransitive (“the parent of,” “the friend of,” etc.).
  • • Intransitivity blocks the logical deduction in a syllogism.

Exercises

Working with Syllogisms and Transitivity

Complete the following exercises:

  1. 1. Draw a relationship between three terms, and revisit the five valid forms and two invalid forms of deductive argument from Chapter 3. Construct versions of each form with three or fewer terms.
  2. 2. Make up a valid syllogistic argument that relies on the transitivity of containment or one of the other transitive relations mentioned above.
  3. 3. Think of another relation you think is transitive, and construct a syllogism to test for validity.
Next Chapter
Chapter 9. Categorical Logic Statements
PreviousNext
Powered by Manifold Scholarship. Learn more at
Opens in new tab or windowmanifoldapp.org
Manifold uses cookies

We use cookies to analyze our traffic. Please decide if you are willing to accept cookies from our website. You can change this setting anytime in Privacy Settings.